Existentialism Defined
Existentialism is a philosophical movement or tendency of the 19th and 20th centuries. Because of the diversity of positions associated with existentialism, a precise definition is impossible;
however, it suggests one major theme: a stress on individual existence and, consequently, on
subjectivity, individual freedom, and choice.
Most philosophers since ancient Greek thinker Plato have held that the highest ethical good is
universal. Nineteenth-century Danish philosopher Søren Kierkegaard reacted against this
tradition, insisting that the individual's highest good is to find his or her own unique vocation.
In terms of moral choice, existentialists have argued that there is no objective, rational basis
for decisions; they stress the importance of individualism in deciding questions of morality and
truth. Most existentialists have held that rational clarity is desirable wherever possible but that
life's most important questions are not accessible to reason or science.
Freedom of choice, through which each human being creates his or her own nature, is a primary
theme. Because individuals are free to choose their own path, existentialists have argued, they
must accept the risk and responsibility of their actions. Kierkegaard held that a feeling of
general apprehension, which he called dread, is God's way of calling each individual to commit
to a personally valid way of life. Relatedly, 20th-century German philosopher Martin Heidegger
felt that anxiety leads to the individual's confrontation with the impossibility of finding
ultimate justification for his or her choices.
The first to anticipate existentialism's major concerns was 17th-century French philosopher
Blaise Pascal, who denounced a systematic philosophy that presumes to explain God and
humanity. He saw life in terms of paradoxes: The human self, combining mind and body, is
itself a contradiction. Later, Kierkegaard rejected a total rational understanding of humanity
and history, stressing the ambiguity and absurdity of the human situation.
Nineteenth-century German philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche espoused tragic pessimism and
life-affirming individual will. Heidegger argued that human beings can never hope to understand why they are here; instead, each individual must choose a goal and follow it with
passionate conviction, aware of the certainty of death and the ultimate meaninglessness of
one's life. Twentieth-century French philosopher Jean Paul Sartre first gave the term existentialism general currency by using it for his own philosophy. Explicitly atheistic and
pessimistic, his philosophy declared that human life requires a rational basis but the attempt is
a "futile passion." Nevertheless, he insisted that his view is a form of humanism, emphasizing
freedom and responsibility.
Although it encompasses atheism and agnosticism, existentialist thought has had a profound
influence on 20th-century theology, addressing such issues as transcendence and the limits of
human experience, as well as a personal sense of authenticity and commitment. Existentialism
has been a vital movement in literature, particularly in the works of Russian novelist Fyodor
Dostoyevsky, Austrian writer Franz Kafka, and French writer Albert Camus. It is also prominent
in the theater of the absurd, notably in the plays of Irish-born writer Samuel Beckett and
Romanian-born French writer Eugène Ionesco. (from Encarta Concise Encyclopedia)
Basic Themes of Existentialism
First Theme...
First, there is the basic existentialist standpoint, that existence precedes essence, has primacy
over essence. Man is a conscious subject, rather than a thing to be predicted or manipulated; he
exists as a conscious being, and not in accordance with any definition, essence, generalization,
or system. Existentialism says I am nothing else but my own conscious existence.
Second existentialist theme...
A second existentialist theme is that of anxiety, or the sense of anguish, a generalized uneasiness, a fear or dread which is not directed to any specific object. Anguish is the dread of the nothingness of human existence. This theme is as old as Kierkegaard within existentialism; it is the claim that anguish is the underlying, all-pervasive, universal condition of
human existence. Existentialism agrees with certain streams of thought in Judaism and
Christianity which see human existence as fallen, and human life as lived in suffering and sin,
guilt and anxiety. This dark and foreboding picture of human life leads existentialists to reject
ideas such as happiness, enlightenment optimism, a sense of well-being, the serenity of
Stoicism, since these can only reflect a superficial understanding of life, or a naive and
foolish way of denying the despairing, tragic aspect of human existence.
Third existentialist theme...
A third existentialist theme is that of absurdity. Granted, says the existentialist, I am my own
existence, but this existence is absurd. To exist as a human being is inexplicable, and wholly
absurd. Each of us is simply here, thrown into this time and place---but why now? Why here?
Kierkegaard asked. For no reason, without necessary connection, only contingently, and so my
life is an absurd contingent fact. Expressive of absurdity are these words by Blaise Pascal, a
French mathematician and philosopher of Descarte's time, who was also an early forerunner of
existentialism. Pascal says:
"When I consider the short duration of my life, swallowed up in the
eternity before and after, and the little space I fill, and even can see,
engulfed in the infinite immensity of space of which I am ignorant,
and which knows me not, I am frightened, and am astonished at being
here rather than there, why now rather than then." --by T. Z. Lavine
Fourth existentialist theme...
The fourth theme which pervades existentialism is that of nothingness or the void. If no
essences define me, and if, then, as an existentialist, I reject all of the philosophies, sciences,
political theories, and religions which fail to reflect my existence as conscious being and
attempt to impose a specific essentialist structure upon me and my world, then there is nothing
that structures my world. I have followed Kierkegaard's lead. I have stripped myself of all
unacceptable structure, the structures of knowledge, moral value, and human relationship, and
I stand in anguish at the edge of the abyss. I am my own existence, but my existence is a
nothingness. I live then without anything to structure my being and my world, and I am looking
into emptiness and the void, hovering over the abyss in fear and trembling and living the life of
dread.
Fifth existentialist theme...
Related to the theme of nothingness is the existentialist theme of death. Nothingness, in the
form of death, which is my final nothingness, hangs over me like a sword of Damocles at each
moment of my life. I am filled with anxiety at times when I permit myself to be aware of this.
At those moments, says Martin Heidegger, the most influential of the German existentialist
philosophers, the whole of my being seems to drift away into nothing. The unaware person tries
to live as if death is not actual, he tries to escape its reality. But Heidegger says that my death
is my most authentic, significant moment, my personal potentiality, which I alone must suffer.
And if I take death into my life, acknowledge it, and face it squarely, I will free myself from
the anxiety of death and the pettiness of life-- and only then will I be free to become myself.
But here the French existentialist Jean-Paul Sartre begs to differ. What is death, he asks?
Death is my total nonexistence. Death is as absurd as birth-- it is no ultimate, authentic moment
of my life, it is nothing but the wiping out of my existence as conscious being. Death is only
another witness to the absurdity of human existence.
Sixth existentialist theme...
Alienation or estrangement is a sixth theme which characterizes existentialism. Alienation is a
theme which Hegel opened up for the modern world on many levels and in many subtle forms.
Thus the Absolute is estranged from itself as it exists only in the development of finite spirit in
historical time. But finite spirit also lives in alienation from its true consciousness of its own
freedom, which it gains only slowly in the dialectic of history. There is also the alienation that
exists in society: the alienation of individual human beings who pursue their own desires in
estrangement from the actual institutional workings of their society, which are controlled by
the Cunning of Reason. Alienated from the social system, they do not know that their desires
are system-determined and system-determining. And there is the alienation of those who do not
identify with the institutions of their own society, who find their society empty and meaningless. And there is also for Hegel the alienation which develops in civil society between
the small class of the wealthy and the growing discontent of the large class of impoverished
workers. The most profound alienation of all in Hegel's thought is the alienation or estrangement between my consciousness and its objects, in which I am aware of the otherness
of the object and seek in a variety of ways to overcome its alienation by mastering it, by
bringing it back into myself in some way.
As for Marx, we have seen that in the split between the two Marxisms, the young Marx is
focused upon the concept of economic alienation. As a worker I am alienated from myself, from
the product of my labor, from the money-worshipping society, from all those social institutions-- family, morality, law, government-- which coerce me into the service of the money-God and keep me from realizing my human creative potentiality. In mature Marxism, alienation is expressed through the division of labor and its many ramifications.
How, then, do existentialists use the concept of alienation? Apart from my own conscious
being, all else, they say, is otherness, from which I am estranged. We are hemmed in by a world
of things which are opaque to us and which we cannot understand. Moreover, science itself has
alienated us from nature, by its outpouring of highly specialized and mathematicized concepts,
laws, theories, and technologies which are unintelligible to the nonspecialist and layman; these
products of science now stand between us and nature. And the Industrial Revolution has
alienated the worker from the product of his own labor, and has made him into a mechanical
component in the productive system, as Marx has taught us.
We are also estranged, say the existentialists, from human institutions-- bureaucratized
government on the federal, state, and local levels, national political parties, giant business
corporations, national religious organizations -- all of these appear to be vast, impersonal
sources of power which have a life of their own. As individuals we neither feel that we are
part of them nor can we understand their workings. We live in alienation from our own
institutions. Moreover, say the existentialists, we are shut out of history. We no longer have a
sense of having roots in a meaningful past nor do we see ourselves as moving toward a
meaningful future. As a result, we do not belong to the past, to the present, or to the future.
And lastly, and perhaps most painfully, the existentialists point out that all of our personal
human relationships are poisoned by feelings of alienation from any "other." Alienation and
hostility arise within the family between parents and children, between the husband and the
wife, between the children. Alienation affects all social and work relations, and most cruelly,
alienation dominates the relationship of love.
These are the disturbing, provocative themes which can be found in contemporary
existentialism. But now we must ask: If this is indeed the human condition, if this is a true
picture of the world in which the human subject absurdly finds himself, how is it possible to go
on living in it? Is there no exit from this anxiety and despair, this nothingness and absurdity,
this fixation upon alienation, this hovering on the edge of the abyss? Is there any existentialist
who can tell us how to live in such an absurd and hopeless world? Is there an existentialist
ethics, a moral philosophy to tell us what is good, what can be said to be right or wrong, in such
a meaningless world? --by T. Z. Lavine
The Human Situation
Heidegger has pointed to the foundation of the intersubjective relationship in dread. When a
man decides to escape from the banality of anonymous existence--which hides the nothingness of existence, or the nonreality of its possibilities, behind the mask of daily concerns--his understanding of this nothingness leads him to choose the only unconditioned and
insurmountable possibility that belongs to him: death. The possibility of death, unlike the
possibilities that relate him to other things and to other men, isolates him. It is a certain
possibility, not through its apodictic evidence but because it continuously weighs upon
existence. To understand this possibility means to decide for it, to acknowledge "the possibility
of the impossibility of any existence at all" and to live for death. The emotive tonality that
accompanies this understanding is dread, through which man feels himself to be "face to face
with the nothing' of the possible impossibility of [his] existence."
But neither the understanding of death nor its emotive accompaniment opens up a specific task
for man, a way to transform his own situation in the world. They enable him only to perceive the
common destiny to which all men are subject; and they offer to him, therefore, the possibility
of remaining faithful to this destiny and of freely accepting the necessity that all men share in
common. In this fidelity consists the historicity of existence, which is the repetition of
tradition, the return to the possibilities from which existence had earlier been constituted, the
wanting for the future what has been in the past. And in this historicity participate not only
man but all of the things of the world, in their utilizability and instrumentality, and even the
totality of Nature as the locus of history.
Dread, therefore, is not fear in the face of a specific danger. It is rather the emotive understanding of the nullity of the possible, or, as Jaspers says, of the possibility of Nothingness. It has, therefore, a therapeutic function in that it leads human existence to its
authenticity. From the fall into factuality into which every project plunges him, man can save
himself only by projecting not to project; i.e., either by abandoning himself decisively to the
situation in which he finds himself or by being indifferent to any possible project--with regard
to which Sartre says, "Thus it amounts to the same thing whether one gets drunk alone or is a
leader of nations."
The pivotal point of that conclusion--the conclusion most widely held among the Existentialists
and the one in fact often identified with Existentialism--is the antithesis between possibility
and reality. On the one hand, existence is interpreted in terms of possibilities that are not
purely logical possibilities or manifestations of a man's ignorance of what exists but are,
rather, effective, or ontic, possibilities that constitute man as such; on the other hand,
contrasted to possibilities in this sense is a reality, a for-itself, a world, a transcendence that
is a factual presence, insurmountable and oppressive, with respect to which possibility is a pure
Nothingness. The contradiction to which this antithesis leads becomes clear when the same
reality is interpreted in terms of possibility: when the being of things, for example, is reduced
to their possibility of being utilized; when the being of other men is reduced to the possibility
of anonymous or personal relationships that the individual can have with them; and when the
being of transcendence, or of God, is reduced to the possibility of the relationship, although
ineffable and mysterious, between transcendence, or God, and man.
It has been said that a coherent Existentialism should avoid the constant mortal leap between
Being and Nothingness; should not confuse the problematic character of existence with the fall
into factuality; should not confuse the finitude of possibilities with resignation to the situation,
choice with determinism; freedom conditioned by the limits of the situation with the
acknowledgment of the omnipresent necessity of the Whole. In this inquiry, it is held,
Existentialism could well benefit from a more attentive consideration of science, which it has
viewed until now only as a preparatory, imperfect, and objectifying knowledge in comparison
with the authentic understanding of Being, which it considers to be a more fundamental mode
of the being of man in the world. Science, it is submitted, offers today the example of an
extensive and coherent use of the concept of the possible in the key notions that it employs,
especially in those branches that are interdisciplinary--among them such notions as
indeterminacy, chance, probability, field, model, project, structure, and conditionality.
Problems of Existentialist Philosophy
The key problems for Existentialism are those of man himself, of his situation in the world, and
of his more ultimate significance. Man and Human Relationships Existentialist anthropology is strictly connected with its ontology. The traditional distinction between soul and body is completely eliminated; thus the body is a lived-through experience that is an integral part of man's existence in its relationship with the world. According to Sartre, "In each project of the For-itself, in each perception the body is there; it is the immediate Past in so far as it still touches on the Present which flees it." As such, however, the body is not reduced to a datum of consciousness, to subjective representation. Consciousness, according to Sartre, is constant openness toward the world, a transcendent relationship with other beings and thereby with the in-itself. Consciousness is existence itself, or, as Jaspers says, it is "the manifestation of being." In order to avoid any subjectivistic equivocation, Heidegger went so far as to renounce the use of the term consciousness, preferring the term Dasein, which is more appropriate for designating human reality in its totality. For the same reasons, the traditional opposition between subject and object, or between the self and the nonself, loses all sense. Dasein is always particular and individual. It is always a self; but it is also always a project of the world that includes the self, determining or conditioning its modes of being.
All of these modes of being thus arise, as Heidegger shows in his masterpiece Sein und Zeit
(1927; Being and Time, 1962), from the relationship between the self and the world. Heidegger
has regarded concern (in the Latin sense of the term) to be the fundamental aspect of this
relationship, insofar as it is man's concern to obtain the things that are necessary for him and
even to transform them with his work as well as to exchange them so as to make them more
suitable to his needs. Concern demonstrates that man is "thrown into the world," into the midst
of other beings, so that in order to project himself he must exist among them and utilize them.
Being thrown means, for man, being abandoned to the whirling flow of things in the world and
to their determinism.
This happens inevitably, according to Heidegger, in inauthentic existence--day-to-day and
anonymous existence in which all behaviour is reduced to the same level, made "official,"
conventional, and insignificant. Chatter, idle curiosity, and equivocation are the characteristics
of this existence, in which "One says this" and "One does that" reign undisputed. Anonymous
existence amounts to a simple "being together" with others, not a true coexistence, which is
obtained only through the acceptance of a common destiny
All of the Existentialists are in agreement on the difficulty of communication; i.e., of
well-grounded intersubjective relationships. Jaspers has perhaps been the one to insist most on
the relationship between truth and communication. Truths are and can be different from
existence. But if fanaticism and dogmatism (which absolutize a historical truth) are avoided on
the one hand while relativism and skepticism (which affirm the equivalence of all truths) are
avoided on the other, then the only other way is a constant confrontation between the
different truths through an always more extended and deepened intersubjective communication.
Parts of the above information is from Encarta Concise Encyclopedia